In what sense is Hegel an Idealist?
In his book, Hegel and Idealism, Karl Americks’
writes that there is no ‘accurate, substantive, and appealing sense in which
Hegel should be regarded as an idealist’1. And
he further argues that claims to regard him as such are ‘extravagant’ and
‘trivial’.
Robert Pippin, on the other
hand, writes that: ‘Hegel followed Kant in attempting to deduce the categories
from the conditions of self-consciousness, to ground them in the “I”’2.
Pippin here provides a reading that interprets Hegel as a kind of
Transcendental Idealist; that is, someone who places priority on the
appearances of the world.
This paper aims to refute
both claims by arguing in defence for an interpretation of Hegel as an Absolute
Idealist. In the first part of the essay
an interpretation of Hegel as an Absolute Idealist will be put forward, and in
the second part, it will address both Americks and Pippins criticisms.
I
Hegel’s Philosophy is,
mainly, a reaction to Kant’s dualistic Philosophy. For Kant, the world is a construct of
cognition: that is, what we see as the world is a perception of the mind and
not the underlying reality. But Hegel
disagrees that the world in it self is ultimately unknowable, claiming it to be
an ‘empty beyond’, since it raises
the problem of how such raw data provides us with our general sensations in the
first place.
Hegel wants to resist such a
division and instead attempt to reconcile ‘concept with reality3’ or as Solomon states: ‘unify man and
nature’4.
Thus, Hegel’s quest is absolute knowledge.
In his Encyclopaedia, Hegel
acknowledged that the absolute is the ‘task of Philosophy’5. The
goal is to come to know the world as it is in it self. Thus, Hegel is attempting to do metaphysics
by pure reason – something Kant would have claimed impossible; but for Hegel
Absolute Idealism provides us with such a possibility.
Hegel defines Absolute
Idealism as ‘the doctrine that things are appearances of the universal divine
idea’ (EPW §24A)6. This reading suggests the absolute as a kind
of God, a spirit in which everything is incorporated, and from which everything
emanates. Therefore, it can be argued
that Hegel adopts a monistic form of idealism in which everything in the world,
including the world itself, is seen as belonging to the essence of an absolute
mind-like substance –namely, to Godi. Indeed, Hegel often stated that the: ‘subject
matter of philosophy is God and God alone’7. Viewed in these terms, Schelling was
wrong to assert that subject and object are one and the same thing. Instead, they are wholly different yet share
the same inherent essence. As Hegel
stated in his Differenzchrift, it is the principal
of subject-object identity that expresses the very spirit of ‘authentic
idealism’ (D, II 9-10/79-80)8. Thus, he is essentially saying that both
subject and object are manifestations of the same thing – that is to say, they
share an identity that binds them to the absolute spirit.
How are we to interpret this
form of idealism? Like Kant, Hegel places priority over mind as the fundamental
corner stone to knowledge, but Hegel’s Absolute Idealism differs from
this. It differs in the sense that:
‘consciousness must have
related itself to the object in accordance with the totality of the latter’s
determinations and have thus grasped it from the standpoint of each of
them. This totality of its
determinations establishes the object as an implicitly spiritual being ’(PS
§788)9.
The idea here is that subject
and object are intrinsically related to each other; they are both mind-like in
essence, and such a connection between the two is implicitly spiritual. This
way Hegel is attempting to merge subject and object together.
If we follow Hegel’s
dialectic - our consciousness striving to progress and develop toward freedom
and perfection - then eventually we will come to the point where mind is at one
with both it self and reality.
Hence, absolute knowing can
be summed up as a ‘spirit that knows itself in the shape of spirit’(PS §798)10, or, in other words, mind coming to
know itself as a form of mind. The
progress of our consciousness comes to an end when we discover that the meaning of life lies within an Absolute
Spirit that is the totality of human consciousness – the Absolute Idea.
II
Karl Americks, as we have
seen, would charge such a view of idealism, or any view of idealism for that
matter, as extravagant and trivial. This
is a very strong and, I think, rather inconsiderate criticism. If Hegel is not an idealist then, equally, he
cannot be a realist or a materialist in any sense because Hegel’s Philosophy
is, in my opinion, absolutely anti-realist in the sense that he sees the
universe as mind-like. He is a monist
along similar lines to Spinoza, as Hegel often refers to spirit or a God as
essence in which everything comes to existence.
Things in the world don’t necessarily exist as separate things to us,
only the Absolute Idea exists. Surely
such a concept is sound for interpreting Hegel as an idealist. Because of his monism, it’s arguable that
this mind-like substance is the
Absolute Idea.
The point, however, is that
Hegel’s enquiry is, fundamentally, human thought. He is attempting to amalgamate human
consciousness with an abstract conception of absolute as consciousness or
spirit. Both these are idealistic
notions; one of the inner subject and the other as an abstract form of idealism
created by his idealism. Contemplating an end of a, potentially, infinite
regress appears troublesome, indeed it seems nigh on impossible, but surely we
must not criticize Hegel for such thinking as absurd or, as Americks puts it,
‘extravagant’. Such thinking can only
come from an idealist in the first place.
But as Robert Stern mentions, why can’t ideas in philosophy be so extravagant?
Surely conceptualising something extravagant requires an extravagant form of
thinking, something which Hegel fits the bill, and it is such thinking which
makes him an Absolute Idealist.
This interpretation may not
be appealing to all, or even correct; but in answering the initial question,
this isn’t to say that he is not an idealist in any sense.
Pippin’s
criticism is, however, a little more damaging than Americks. He sees Hegel as, basically, a Transcendental
Idealist, one who grounds the experiences through the “I”.
Indeed,
such a reading is not prima facie misleading. Hegel begins his phenomenology by placing
consciousness as the starting point of knowledge, so, in a sense, progress must
be a condition of what the mind sees.
But
the difficulty with such a reading begins with, as we have seen, Hegel’s
rejection of the Kantian realm of the thing in it self or the empty
beyond. Indeed to claim Hegel as a
Transcendental Idealist implies that Hegel is restricted to the world of his
own mind and that such raw data transcend from his notion of the ‘empty beyond’
which he initially wanted to get rid of.
However, in reply, it could be argued that since the world as it is in
it self is not knowable within the confines of human experience, then Hegel’s
conduct of metaphysics is utilized in a transcendental manner, since we can’t
escape our minds eye. In saying that, it
could also be argued that philosophizing about the world as it appears to be, implies an unknowable world providing us
with the appearances in the first place.
So why can’t we say that we are experiencing and knowing the world as it
really is instead? This is, in essence, Hegel’s argument for the Absolute. We do know the world as it really is because
our mind comes to realize that it is the builder of reality, and that the
source of our mind and everything else comes from the Absolute mind in which
everything is connected with implicitly. Therefore, although there are perceptive
differences and different levels of conscious awareness amongst human and
animal, we share one underlying ‘cosmic conscious’11 – the absolute idea. For example, a cup may look different to each
of us, but most people would agree that there are inherent similarities that we
all share about the cup; for example its use.
Likewise, with animals there are similarities we have in common such as
hunger, emotional needs and an intimate sense of connection; for example, with
particular pets we share a mutual level of understanding. Although the level of consciousness varies,
the connection between consciousness is
absolute mind.
Therefore
there must be something universal that provides us with such a bond. For Hegel then, both subjects and objects are
grounded within the inherent spirit
of the Absolute in which everything is a part of; his Absolute Idealism allows
us to become implicitly aware of such a bond.
Hence things are not strictly grounded in Pippin’s loosely defined
notion of the “I”.
Hegel,
thus, is an Absolute Idealist because he allows his mind to progress in an
unlimited way. A way in which other
forms of idealism does not allow.
If such an interpretation of
Hegel as an Absolute Idealist is accepted, then surely this leaves a
metaphysical enquiry into the nature of the absolute, but Hegel states:
‘the terminus [of the absolute] is at that
point where knowledge is no longer compelled to go beyond itself’ (PS §80)12.
So, such thoughts, whatever
they be, are already within the absolute.
The terminus is true knowledge of everything as a complete whole in
which, at that point, we can’t venture beyond it because there is no obligation
to. But the difficulty is that we just
can’t imagine this!
Perhaps the problem with
Hegel’s idea is his insistence that we can ‘know’
the world as it really is, for this implies that we are explicitly certain
about it; but clearly this is not the case.
Instead we re compelled to
know it implicitly.
But, as Schleiermacher
mentioned, knowledge of the Absolute is more a ‘matter of feeling’13 or hunch that there is something
unconditionally knowable that we and everything else are an essential part.
A Wittgensteinian may argue
that this is a matter of language going on holiday (PI §38)14, but this would be to impose that the
problem is with our own thinking, and that there is no meaning to the
universe. Indeed there might not be any
meaning in an anthropomorphic sense, but because we can’t justify meaning
humanly, is not to say that there is no meaning at all.
To summarize the argument,
Hegel is an Absolute Idealist in the sense that he incorporates subject and
object as mind-like. That our
consciousness is essentially the creator of reality and that such reality is
conditioned upon the Absolute Idea which is unconditioned.
He is not an idealist in a
subjective nor transcendental sense as he finds these as heavily one
sided.
Although Pippin argues that
he follows on from Kant’s metaphysics, a more accurate interpretation shows
that even though Hegel incorporates it as part of his quest for Absolute
knowledge, essentially he reacts to it as an incomplete system.
As Americks doesn’t interpret
Hegel as an idealist in any sense, it is more unlikely that he is either a
realist or materialist in any sense, since he is very much adamant about an
underlying essence from which everything becomes into being.
Effectively, therefore, Hegel
jumps from a limited form of thinking to an unlimited
one, and it is this leap that makes him an Absolute Idealist.
© 2011 Roberto Nacci All Rights Reserved
References
1 Karl Americks, Hegel and
Idealism, The Monist, 74 (1991) , pp. 386-402 p.397
2 Robert B. Pippin, Hegel’s
Idealism: The satisfaction of Self-consciousness (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1989), p. 7.
3 G.W.F. Hegel, Lectures on the History of Philosophy, In Robert. C
Solomon, In the Spirit of Hegel
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983), p, 176
4 Robert. C. Solomon, In the
Spirit of Hegel, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1983), p. 23
5 Frederick Beiser, Hegel
(Oxon: Routledge, 2005), p. 54
6 G.W.F. Hegel, The
Encyclopedia Logic, Part I of the Encyclopedia of Philosophical Sciences,
In Beiser (2005), p. 57
7Beiser, op. cit., p.54.
8Beiser, op. cit., p. 62
9 G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology
of Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller. (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1977)
10 ibid. p
11 Peter Singer, Hegel, In Roger Scruton, Peter Singer, Christopher
Janaway, and Michale Tanner, German
Philosophers. Kant, Hegel, Schopenhauer, and Nietzsche ( Oxford: Oxford
University Press (1997) p. 177
12 G.W.F. Hegel op. cit, §80
13 Solomon, op. cit., p.85
14 G.E.M. Anscombe
and R.Rhees (1953), Philosophical
Investigations, Oxford: Blackwell
2 comments:
I am extremely impressed with your writing skills as well
as with the layout on your weblog. Is this a paid theme or
did you modify it yourself? Either way keep up the nice
quality writing, it is rare to see a great blog like
this one nowadays.
my homepage ... acrylic ()
Thank you very much for your comment, I am glad you like my blog. This is a free blog so I do all the writing and the layout myself. Most of the essays I have on here were written at university, so I decided to upload them as a way of keeping them in one central location.
Unfortunately I cannot find your homepage, can you send me the link??
Post a Comment